Saturday, December 13, 2008
Illinois and the Constitutional Crisis
The constitutional issue du jour is whether the Illinois Supreme Court can grant the state injunctive relief and prevent Blagojevich from carrying out his office's duties. In a motion filed with Illinois's highest court yesterday, the attorney general filed a request for a temporary restraining order and/or preliminary injunction. The people, through the attorney general, are claiming that Blagojevich is unable to serve "due to disability and should not rightfully continue to hold that office."
What a fascinating course of action! Of course, even the governor's critics are rather stunned at the idea of injunctive relief being sought against the highest executive officer in Illinois. The motion itself is quite weak, relying on Article V of Illinois's Constitution. Any fair reading of section 5 gives the power to the Illinois legislature. Of course, the supreme court is given exclusive and original jurisdiction in the event that no law is in place, but it is a stretch to consider this carte blanche for the Supreme Court to decide when the governor is fit or unfit to serve.
Commentators are already saying that the Illinois justices are traditionally cautious and most likely will not grant this motion. But then again, courts have done stranger things...
Saturday, November 8, 2008
Obama, Security, and Sham History
Some would rather these times weren't this historic. Bill Kristol at the Weekly Standard has written a somewhat (less than) generous opinion piece lamenting that more of the country didn't see things his way. He is concerned that we, as a country, are now suddenly at a greater security risk than we would have had a septuagenarian and his girl-novice sidekick been elected.
I grant Kristol his opinion. But his justification comes from a bizarre historical narrative. He suggests that the American electorate has, since WWII, followed a consistent pattern in voting. Republican administrations make us strong and feared about the world, and then we feel happy enough to elect Democratic presidents who muck things up by being soft and squishy.
Consider:
Encouraging Americans' tendency to take hard-won national security successes for granted--once they are won--is the key to how Democrats, in modern times, win presidential elections. Dwight Eisenhower pursued a cautious but not ineffective foreign policy. Voters were unimpressed by the peace and stability of 1960 and chose John Kennedy. Partly as a result of Kennedy's initial weakness, the Berlin Wall went up and the Cuban Missile Crisis followed--and then, partly out of a felt need of Lyndon Johnson's to appear strong, we escalated in Vietnam.Let us forget for a moment that Eisenhower was elected primarily to extricate America from an unpopular war started by a fist-pounding Democrat, and that Kennedy campaigned as a stanch cold-warrior to the more moderate Nixon. Let us forget that the Soviets did not need anyone's permission to build the Berlin Wall and weren't "waiting around" to do it. Let's keep our eye on the larger narrative. Kristol continues:
The voters elected Richard Nixon to extricate us from the quagmire in Vietnam with honor, which he did, and Gerald Ford attempted to prevent the Democratic Congress from walking away from our ally and our responsibility. Voters decided, however, to give the presidency back to the party of JFK and LBJ--by this time more the party of George McGovern--and we got the Iranian revolution and the Soviet invasion of Afghanistan.Kristol is right that we elected Nixon to extricate ourselves from Vietnam, presumably with honor. He ended up bombing Cambodia. The bombing continued for years before he left with the same terms he could have gotten at the beginning of his tenure as president. Given the recent evidence that Kissenger may have sabotaged the peace talks under Johnson in order to prolong the war for an incoming Nixon administration, the idea of Nixon's failed Vietnam policy amounting to "peace with honor" is something of a joke. The Iranian Revolution occurred--if I read Kristol correctly--because we were not hard enough on Iran? As if the secret police we trained for the Shah and the support we gave him to keep Iran a client state was not enough. Would he prefer we had provided more weapons of repression to that regime? Does he really suppose that the Iranian revolutionaries cared who was president back in the United States? Nor did the election of Ronald Reagan do anything to convince the Soviets to leave Afghanistan. And the USSR's protracted presence in Afghanistan played its part in its own demise--a lesson we may want to take to heart before we jump into any more wars in the name of strength and national security.So Americans elected Ronald Reagan and George H.W. Bush, and--stunningly--they won the Cold War virtually without firing a shot. (Bush also drove Saddam Hussein from Kuwait.) Voters were able in 1992 to take peace for granted and to focus on domestic policy. "It's the economy, stupid" was stupid but successful just as its equivalents had been in 1976 and 1960.
What is most disheartening about Kristol's analysis are the assumptions that govern it. Events that occur during a presidency--carefully selected and pruned of any meaningful context--are attributed to the sitting president. One could just as easily construct a counter-narrative which is even more compelling.
Start with World War II, instead of avoiding it as Kristol does. Our Democratic president and his Democratic successor achieved the impossible: getting powerful, industrialized fascist countries to surrender unconditionally. Harry Truman, in his zeal to stop the totalitarian Soviet Union from expanding its reach, combatted communism in Korea. The American people, confident that we were powerful enough to stand some peace, elected Dwight D. Eisenhower. By the end of his term, the Soviet Union had achieved the H-Bomb, was more powerful than ever, and ready to move on Berlin and Cuba. Americans elected John F. Kennedy--a chest-thumping cold warrior--over the more moderate and level-headed Richard Nixon. Kennedy met the Russians face-to-face and took us to the brink of nuclear war in order to defend freedom, including engaging in a hot war in Vietnam. Nixon would be elected in 1968 to extricate us from the war, much as Eisenhower had before him. Nixon ended up pursuing a policy of appeasment with communist Russia and communist China. Reagan's administration fared no better than Carter's, given our meager victory in Grenada and the more substantial embarrassment that was Lebanon.I could go on, but there is no point. The counter-narrative is just as empty and inspid as Kristol's narrative. I use it only as a heuristic device, and only to demonstrate that Barack Obama's election does not signal that a confident public believes it has been protected by the last administration and now is ready to "take a chance." Many Americans rightly believe that this last, failed presidency has seriously weakened us as a country, that we can no longer defend ourselves the way we might have eight years ago. Kristol's inability to acknowledge this simple truth is, on his part, both an intellectual and a moral failure.
Monday, November 3, 2008
Guantanamo, War, and the Rule of Law
Elections are constitutional moments, and 2008 is something special in this regard. But we should not lose sight of the fact that one of the most important constitutional issues of our day was decided in the months leading up to this election, when the Republican Party made John McCain and not Mitt Romney its candidate. Romney, we should recall, promised to "double" Guantanamo. He repeatedly invoked the stark language of "good" and "evil" in his foreign policy discussions. And despite these moral absolutisms, he was not willing to repudiate the use of torture.
One constitutional issue for the electorate to decide has, therefore, been decided already. It is up to all of us now--or at least those of us who wish to see our government restored to lawful, rational, and moral behavior--to hold the next president accountable. Guantanamo must be closed, and the prisoners there either released or charged with crimes.
See you all on the 5th.
Saturday, November 1, 2008
Not an endorsement, really...
Meanwhile, I still harbor tremendous doubts about the Republican choice for President. Sadly, much of this comes from McCain's selection of Sarah Palin, who has now been identified by some as the "hope" of the Republican Party. If this is true, then the Republican Party deserves the drubbing it will receive on November 4. It deserves to become a permanent minority party. As George Will--in something a little more than a statement of good will and a little less than an endorsement of Obama--put it:
Some polls show that Palin has become an even heavier weight in John McCain's saddle than his association with George W. Bush. Did McCain, who seems to think that Palin's never having attended a "Georgetown cocktail party" is sufficient qualification for the vice presidency, lift an eyebrow when she said that vice presidents "are in charge of the United States Senate"?
She may have been tailoring her narrative to her audience of third-graders, who do not know that vice presidents have no constitutional function in the Senate other than to cast tie-breaking votes. But does she know that when Lyndon Johnson, transformed by the 1960 election from Senate majority leader into vice president, ventured to the Capitol to attend the Democratic senators' weekly policy luncheon, the new majority leader, Montana's Mike Mansfield, supported by his caucus, barred him because his presence would be a derogation of the Senate's autonomy?
Perhaps Palin's confusion about the office for which she is auditioning comes from listening to its current occupant. Dick Cheney, the foremost practitioner of this administration's constitutional carelessness in aggrandizing executive power, regularly attends the Senate Republicans' Tuesday luncheons. He has said jocularly that he is "a product" of the Senate, which pays his salary, and that he has no "official duties" in the executive branch. His situational constitutionalism has, however, led him to assert, when claiming exemption from a particular executive order, that he is a member of the legislative branch and, when seeking to shield certain of his deliberations from legislative inquiry, to say that he is a member of the executive branch.
McCain has been careless in this campaign, and it does not bode well for America should he be elected. He seems to fly by the seat of his pants, makes decisions from the gut, and has abandoned his former virtues of moderation, independent thought, and coolness. The Economist opined the same sentiment when it endorsed Obama earlier this week--the editors clearly pined for the old McCain, but cannot see him leading in any real way as President.
As a constitutional scholar concerned about the preservation of rule of law in this republic and the advancement of human rights worldwide, it matters less to me who is president than what the next president does. Personally, I can't wait until this election is over. It has been exciting, but it is quickly approaching tedious. I'm looking forward to casting my ballot on Tuesday. I'm then looking forward to holding whoever is elected to account for his actions for the next four years. And I would like to see some constituitonal history in the making, reversing the trends begun by Bush, Cheney, and that lawless crew that has run the White House like it was a biker bar for the past eight years.
Monday, October 27, 2008
Election Fraud and the Justice Department
On its face, this appears to be reasonable. Except that we have three contextualizing factors:
1. George W. Bush's Justice Department has been the most notoriously partisan of any recent administration, and "voter fraud" was the entering wedge that U.S. attorneys were supposed to use to disenfranchise people who were predisposed to vote Democratic. In case anyone forgot, this brought down Attorney General Albert Gonzales and shamed the administration. It led James Bovard to call for Bush's impeachment.
2. It has been a long-time tactic of Republicans to set up as many roadblocks as possible to prevent registered Democrats from voting. The usual saying is that Democrats do a better job of registering voters and Republicans do a better job of getting those voters to the polls. Perhaps Democrats would be better about voting if they didn't find that their registrations had been "lost" or destroyed, as in Fulton County (my county of residence, by the way) where 70,000 new registrations were found in the trash.
3. We are eight days from an election. For Ohio Republicans to attempt to disenfranchise 200,000 new voters--and for the President to suggest an investigation at this point--smacks of a cynical last minute ploy to keep Democrats sitting next Tuesday. If nothing else, the President ought to maintain an air of impartiality in the execution of his official duties. But then again, this president has exhibited an unprincipled ignorance of our Constitution, when not treating it with outright contempt.
Wednesday, October 15, 2008
Your Highness, the President of the United States
The dispensing power in executive authority is not new. James II claimed it in 1685 when he became King of England. Parliament called him to account by ousting him from the throne. The resulting constitutional settlement--the Glorious Revolution of 1688-89--crimped executive royal power for good.
The president is, in many ways, an elected king. The president wields a powerful veto on legislation, commands the armed forces, and directs the execution of our nation's laws. We have seen the powers of this office grow in the twentieth century. The president now commands armies in peacetime as well as in war, and sets policy and often times the agenda for Congress. If the president can add to his list of powers the ability to dispense with parts of laws, we may have moved backward in time to the seventeenth century conception of a monarchy.
We are watching constitutional change in its incipient form. The signing statements have not the force of law unless courts begin accepting them as authoritative. The next president has not yet been elected, so we do not know if the practice will die away or continue unabated.
So, stay tuned.
Sunday, October 12, 2008
Legal Theory and Cosmopolitanism: Identity and Its Discontents
“And when one day our human kind becomes full-grown, it will not define itself as the sum total of the whole world's inhabitants, but as the infinite unity of their mutual needs.”
- Jean-Paul Sartre
The philosophy that led sociologist C. Wright Mills to his many insights of American life in the first half of the 20th century was arguably his belief in the Sociological Imagination.—The practice of tying the individual experience with institutions and a focus on the relationship between biography and history to bring about a fuller understanding of the individual and/or the society which she is a part of. To be sure, this notion of attaching the concept of empathy to distant individuals to bring about organic understanding is not particularly new, though perhaps forgotten in our times of curious contradiction.
Historian Lynn Hunt argues that the epistolary advent of the novel in the 18th century had physical effects (citing Richardson’s Pamela and Clarissa and Rousseau’s Julie) which created new concepts on the organization of social and political life. It is with these broadening feelings of empathy that feelings or rights in our time have grown to become largely “self-evident.” Prior to the beginning of the epistolary novel, Dr. Hunt argues, attention hadn’t been focused on how individual minds understand and reshape social and cultural contexts.
Reaching further back still, Roman Emperor Marcus Aurelius, last of the “five good emperors”, starts his Meditations (originally written as entries in a personal notebook) by listing all the people whom he learned something worthwhile from: “From my father I observed mildness of temper and unchangeable resolution in the things which he had determined after due deliberation….” Above all, perhaps, Aurelius’ Mediations are replete with the finite nature of human life and the infinite nature of the universe. When one realizes this cosmology, Aurelius argues that the proper course one should take is the labor to common interest and to value everything with just reference to the whole. Since his death in 180 AD, the Meditations have been read and have influenced millions of people including Chinese Premier Wen Jiabao.
I briefly cite these examples (with an admitted bias to Marcus Aurelius) to show that examining the relationship between the individual and society has brought tremendous insight and principles of advancement through human history—particularly in the rights and privileges we all know and experience on some level today. In many ways, our Arts and Humanities education is directed to studying or at least developing concepts which enable us to think about others. Our economy, as we are seeing, is inextricably tied to those of other countries as we share in the weal and woe of development, coexistence, and stability.
There is much to be said about this concept of empathy and the recognition of the dynamic biographical history of individuals in relation to the socio-cultural contexts in which they live—particularly if there have been instances overtime that have led to a leveling of society which benefits all. In attempts not to lineate the many facets and forms of empathy that exist, there are institutions such as the legal and its schools of thought that arguably, in their attempts to discern by ascribing a theoretical equality of all individuals, disregard or singularize the individual experience in relation to socio-cultural history. In order to further carry my position, I will be citing Eric A. Posner’s essay analyzing Boumediene v. Bush, “Boumediene and the Uncertain March of Judicial Cosmopolitanism.”
In Boumediene v. Bush, the Supreme Court held that noncitizens detained at Guantanamo Bay have the constitutional privilege of habeas corpus and that the review procedures established by the Detainee Treatment Act do not provide a sufficient substitute for habeas corpus. Posner argues that Justice Kennedy’s opinion (which he wrote for the majority) is largely due to a commitment to protecting the interests of noncitizens overseas—a commitment he calls “judicial cosmopolitanism.” Posner’s conclusion and critique of Justice Kennedy rests on the idea of an American political community of which people outside are denied certain rights. This harkens back to a disagreement I have with many ideal theorists (mainly Rawls) whose conception of a political community rests on a closed state that one is born into and can never leave. Furthermore, he cites logistic difficulties in granting habeas corpus rights dealing with cost, difficulty, and a dangerous setting for the military to comply with requirements of a habeas hearing.
Posner argues that Justice Kennedy places all weight on the logistical concern and perhaps none on the political community concern. While the case against a logistics argument is admittedly weak as stated by Posner (since Guantanamo Bay is about 500 miles away from Florida), Justice Kennedy notes that the habeas court will give deference to the government where deference is justified and the argument that habeas hearings are logistically unreasonable is, until experience proves otherwise, foreclosed. Posner then further criticizes Kennedy for not taking the “natural” assumption that “nonresident aliens just don’t have the rights Americans have.” Which almost begs the question, just what is an “American right” and what makes it so exclusive that all should not possess them if our goal in the legal system is to distinguish truth and fairness from fallacy—particularly in a time where crimes are committed against America are coming from those all over the world?
His conclusion for Justice Kennedy’s reasoning?
…Justice Kennedy is a Cosmopolitan.
Here, by Posner, and taken in a similar route by Rawls and others, we have the curious avenues one can take to articulate theories of justice. By taking the identity of an individual and her place in society and either disregarding it and placing them in an either/or situation so long as rights are concerned, as Posner does, or singularizing them (as with Rawls) by limiting the individual to a closed society and only able to belong to that community, we have curious makings of a habit of unwillingness to deal with human complexity. If we are to uphold a just and fair legal system in a post 9/11 world where even our presidential candidates are being called terrorists by fellow citizens, while our government sends billions for oil to many people who would do us harm, and where labeling carries a certain disregard for and singularizes identity. It is becoming clear in more ways than one that our current conceptions of human ecology and identity may not serve us justly for the future.
Saturday, October 11, 2008
An Open Letter to John McCain
I understand in recent weeks that your campaign has come on hard times. I understand it must be frustrating to find a ten-year quest for the White House—what was clearly a lifelong ambition on your part—impeded by a relative newcomer with whom you have serious philosophical disagreements. As such, I understand why you have abandoned promises to make this election about ideas and policies and instead committed the kind of character assault that was used so successfully against you in 2000. Such turns are, however regrettable, to be expected in electoral politics. We can trace such history back to our first seriously contested presidential election in 1800. They are nothing new, and simply a part of democratic politics, however ugly.
I write this with a somewhat heavy heart. I have blogged in support of your kind of conservatism in the past—you are one of the last Republicans left in the party with whom I felt kinship. I was excited about campaign in 2000 and have deeply lamented in the last years that we have lived with a Bush rather than a McCain White House. I have even been willing to accept your genuflection to the radical right. I wrote this off as the kind of coalition building necessary to generate a majority rather than a compromise of your principles. I was elated when you won the Republican primary because I believed it a victory for the decency wing of the Republican Party.
Nonetheless, nothing can justify the behavior of some of the people in your rallies who have, in reference to Obama, shouted such things as “Traitor!” “Terrorist!” and “Kill him!” Your campaign has now released several statements defending these incendiary words, rather than distancing you from them.
Character assaults, however petty, may be justified as political necessity. But to countenance calls for murder is unconscionable. We live in an age where the possibility of political violence in the form of terrorism exists everywhere in the world. It is, as many have suggested, our greatest challenge. We may not be able to extinguish political violence in our time—such thought is of course Pollyannaish—but we can at least take a principled stand on the matter. You should. I urge you to be uncompromising on this matter, to reject such comments from even your supporters. It would set the right tone in an uncertain age.
I don’t know if these suggestions are politically intelligent, or would resonate with voters, or help you in swing states. I am not a political strategist. But I believe the moral principle here more important for our future than the tactics you employ to win an election. After all, doesn’t country come first?
With respect,
H. Robert Baker
Friday, October 3, 2008
Palin, Biden and what does a constitutional office entail, anyway?
The question came long into the debate, when both candidates appeared fatigued. Palin had just explained her understanding of the role of vice-president in relation to the president. McCain has already signaled, apparently, that she would head up energy policy and "reform of government over all" and working with families with special needs. Biden answered that he was a man of independent judgment, but that he was working for Barack Obama.
Gwen Ifill, the moderator, then asked a question which appeared to be something like a spontaneous follow up. (Here's the transcript I'm working with, by the way). "Governor, you mentioned a moment ago the constitution might give the vice president more power than it has in the past. Do you believe as Vice President Cheney does, that the Executive Branch does not hold complete sway over the office of the vice presidency, that it is also a member of the Legislative Branch?"
This gets to the crux of the issue. And while both candidates have doubtlessly been boning up on policy subjects, this straying into a constitutional matter may have tested their substantive understanding of the Constitution. It is an important question, given that the officer we ultimately elect is not just a policy wonk, but someone charged with defending and protecting the Constitution. Here was Palin's answer:
Well, our founding fathers were very wise there in allowing through the Constitution much flexibility there in the office of the vice president. And we will do what is best for the American people in tapping into that position and ushering in an agenda that is supportive and cooperative with the president's agenda in that position. Yeah, so I do agree with him that we have a lot of flexibility in there, and we'll do what we have to do to administer very appropriately the plans that are needed for this nation. And it is my executive experience that is partly to be attributed to my pick as V.P. with McCain, not only as a governor, but earlier on as a mayor, as an oil and gas regulator, as a business owner. It is those years of experience on an executive level that will be put to good use in the White House also.Huh? I'm not sure which founding father deserves credit for imbuing the office of vice president with "flexibility," but I'm sure he would be surprised to find this out. Of course, invoking the "wisdom" of the founding fathers is always a more political than intellectual argument, and as such we should not take that so seriously. In truth, Palin did not answer the question. This is a dodge that has become typical of her when she is cornered--she meanders, then tries to say something about her experience as a mayor or a mother. In this case, she went with mayor/governor, to highlight "executive" experience.
Biden's response was emphatic. He rejected Vice President Cheney's interpretation of the Constitution as dangerous. He then gave a somewhat confusing answer about where the vice president's office is defined in the Constitution, citing "Article I" but saying it is an executive office. If I followed him correctly, he was saying that Article I only gives the VP one role when he presides over the Senate, and that is to cast a vote in the event of a tie.
At this point, I wish Biden had tried to pin down Palin. He studiously avoided doing anything that would come off as condescending (possibly to avoid cries of sexism). This may have been a good political move, but someone needed to get Palin to answer the question: do you believe, as does Cheney, that the office of Vice President is not under the sway of the executive? That it is an independent office that exists neither in the executive or legislative branches?
I have blogged in the past about my concern over McCain's selection of Palin. VPs are usuallly ciphers, but given McCain's advanced age and 100 plus pages of medical report, Palin has to demonstrate she is ready. She has given a series of shaky interviews in the past few weeks suggesting that she is out of her depth on the national stage. Now, in the only part of the debate that asked the candidates to display a substantive understanding of the Constitution, she has stumbled again. She is not yet "a heartbeat away from the presidency." But if she someday is, then my only advice: be afraid.
Friday, September 26, 2008
Brinksmanship and the Debates
At some point on Sep. 24, a conference call between the two campaigns ended with the suggestion of a joint statement that Congress should put aside divisions and figure out a plan for the current financial crisis.
John McCain made a prepared, public announcement later that day saying he was suspending his campaign and asking that the presidential debate be postponed.
Obama responded that the debates did not need to be delayed. He suggested that the time was ripe for a debate and that presidents need to multitask anyway.
McCain has further said he will not participate in the debate unless a consensus has been reached in Congress about the bailout plan.
This narrative changes by the minute, so this is already out of date. But the narrative is a curious look at politics on the campaign trail. It is, either sadly or gleefully, a parody of itself.
Nothing is funny about the financial crisis, except that the response seems to be to give the former CEO of Goldman-Sachs $700 billion in seed money without any legislative or judicial oversight or review. This is a page out of the FDR playbook, which tells us something about the constitutional direction of the new conservative movement.
But the response of the candidates is. First, John McCain reads from a teleprompter a statement saying that this has surprised us all and that we have to drop everything to guarantee a legislative solution. Let's drop politics, he says, and suspends his campaign.
Except that there is nothing more political than telling the nation that you are not political and (arguably, I know) using the crisis as a platform for a campaign slogan ("Country First"). And I doubt anyone really thinks otherwise. Certainly Obama didn't, who took the opportunity to remind everyone that the president needs to be vigorous and should be able to lift heavy objects and leap buildings and the like. The obvious implication is that McCain lacks such vigor. A clever, if somewhat mean, counterstroke.
But McCain then upped the ante by saying he WOULDN'T participate in the debate unless a consensus was reached. This is pure brinksmanship. He is virtually daring Obama to fly to the debate alone, and then have to turn his plane around for Washington.
But will it work? If McCain backs down and goes to the debates, he will have backed down (unless he can sell a compromise in the next eight hours, which is . . .). If he doesn't go, it's a huge gamble. Will it pay off?
Meanwhile, we're getting a taste of what the next president will have to deal with.
Thursday, September 18, 2008
Cosmopolitan Judging and Habeas Corpus
If one separates his analysis of Boumediene to his critique of cosmopolitan judging, then we have the makings of a new debate in constitutional law. For better or worse, conservatives seem to line up in the "American exceptionalism" and positivist camps, adhering to originalism in constitutional construction. Liberals seem (also for better or worse) to be more interested in global human rights and the symbiotic relationship between American constituitonal law and global law. Posner's essay, while not particularly deep, is an excellent introduction to these ideas, and offers a conservative, thoughtful critique of cosmopolitan judging.
One effect of continually appointing strict originalists and positivists to the bench (people like Scalia and Alito) is that their palpable disdain for foreign law in an increasingly global era has lessened the influence of the Supreme Court internationally. The Court used to be the gold standard for constitutional law, but it is now in decline. Not that this signals an immediate need to admit foreign law into Supreme Court opinions--and certainly not as controling law--but we must be honest about the consequences of judicial parochialism as well as judicial cosmopolitanism.
Monday, September 15, 2008
Cosmopolitanism and the Revenge of Logicalitiness
It feels good to take a breather from the madness.
Sunday, September 14, 2008
Elections and Constitutional Regimes
Probably not. But before we analyze that, we need to lay some historical groundwork. There are very few national elections that we might call constitutionally transformative in our history. I would argue for the following elections as fitting within that category: 1800; 1860; 1896; 1936. Each of these elections brought not just policy change, but serious and new interpretations of the Constitution to bear against older alternatives. 1800, of course, makes the case for itself: the Federalists and the Democratic-Republicans cast the election in those terms, and there is no doubt that Jefferson's election set the terms for constitutional interpretation for the next sixty years. The unresolved question of the antebellum era was slavery, and those issues came to a head in the election of 1860, when a party won that was devoted to keeping slavery from the federal territories. It brought Civil War. The 1896 election was noted for the losers--the Populists. The subsequent co-opting of progressive reform into the Republican Party created the activist, muscular government (think Teddy after 1900) that enforced rules that the Supreme Court had attempted to subvert. Finally, 1936 was a repudiation of the Lochner-era laissez faire Constitution and the ushering in of the New Deal.
This is not to say that other elections have not had huge political impact. 1828 marked the birth of democratic participation in the presidential election; 1876 signaled the end of Reconstruction; 1912 demonstrated how divided the United States was (given that the socialist candidate netted a big percentage of the vote); 1968 spelled the end of Democratic dominance of national issues; 1980 brought conservatism into the mainstream. But these political changes (I would argue) did not necessarily auger the kind of constitutinal change that we might describe as transformative. They may have been transformative politically, but (to take but one example) the Reagan mantra of low taxes and higher defense spending was not in-and-of-itself a novel interpretation of the Constitution meant to replace rival views. It was, more properly, a policy disagreement with liberal democrats.
To return to 2008. I had initially imagined that *perhaps* we were living in a transformative age. The Bush White House has through a variety of means exerted executive power in new ways. When combined with a quiescent Congress (even after that Congress turned Democrat) it appeared that we were more and more coming within the gambit of an imperial presidency. The stakes, therefore, for this election seemed inordinately high. Would the next president augment that power, or bring the office within constitutional limits?
These issues, however, do not seem to animate the electorate. Not that they need to, of course--many of those who voted for Lincoln did not do so in order to change the Constitution. Nonetheless, the nation understood his electoral victory as the kind of mandate that would remove federal protection (and sponsorship) of slavery. It was enough to drive the slaveholding states to secession. And from their perspective, rightfully so. They saw the imminent end of slavery, even if that imminent end was not immediate emancipation, but rather the slow strangulation provided by refusing slaveholders access to western territories.
In this election, thus, we are confronted with a question that does not have an easy answer. Is anyone really concerned with the executive branch's grab for power in the past eight years? Are we concerned that our own civil liberties might be endangered by the Bush administration's (and Congress's) end-run around the suspension clause? (I refer here to the issues raised in Boumediene v. Bush, and encourage anyone interested in this subject to read my article in common-place about it.) Polls have focused either on the economy or Iraq, and news coverage has steadily ignored all constitutional issues, excepting abortion. (Mainstream coverage of this has, as usual, been awful.)
It was possible several months ago to see both Obama's candidacy and McCain's victory over Romney in the Republican primary as an indication that American voters were moving not just toward a new kind of politics, but repudiating the executive powermongers understanding of the Constitution.
I do not believe it is possible to view things that way now. Nonetheless, we are caught in the fog of war and perhaps this election might nonetheless prove transformative. But that will require statesmen to emerge amongst those (whomever they are) who win the election. It has happened before, of course. But there are also reasons that we have come to expect so little from politicians.
Thursday, September 4, 2008
Sketch of a Villain
Excuse, if you will, a few disconnected thoughts about the Republican National Convention: about Palin, Huckabee, and (sadly disturbingly) Mitt Romney.
Sarah Palin, the surprise pick for VP, did not surprise anyone with her speech. Well delivered and strong, full of falsehoods and half-truths: everything we have come to expect from a VP. If she survives the ethics investigation in her home state (they are, after all, REPUBLICANS who are investigating her and most likely will fall into line before recommending censure or impeachment for her clear ethics violations), she will get the base foaming at the mouth.
Huckabee made one revealing statement in what was otherwise a boring speech. He praised McCain for never renouncing his country while a POW in Vietnam. If he had just renounced his country, said Huckabee, he could have gone home early. This is not the way I understand the story. McCain did break under torture and did sign a statement saying he was a war criminal and an air pirate (or whatever they shoved under his nose). His heroism came from his refusal to leave the camp before POWs who had arrived before him were released. I find such a story tremendously moving, as it does recommend McCain's character. Sadly (for Huckabee or whoever wrote his speech) it doesn't comport well enough with the "country first" theme of the Convention.
Mitt Romney is fast emerging as the Republican villain. His speech was replete with meaningless platitudes. He tried to whip up a frenzy over radical Islam, suggesting that George Bush did the right thing by labeling certain countries part of an axis of evil and starting a war in one of them. (This got surprisingly few cheers, by the way.) He took a backhanded swipe at Michelle Obama. And he castigated as liberal the establishment at Washington--an establishment that has been resoundingly republican for the last fourteen years. And there is simply something frightening about a man who says that the Democrats are the party of "Big Brother" yet scolds the Supreme Court (apparently a liberal bulwark, in Romney's pea-brained world) for upholding habeas corpus against the doctrine of unlimited executive power.
For the constitutional scholar, Mitt Romney is the villain. He is the partisan without thought-out principles. He promotes power rather than limits on power. His understanding of foreign affairs is mean spirited and, sadly, seems to animate a small portion of our population. His principles are on the edge of unacceptability--he ought to be tossed out by any legitimate political party, not given a prime spot at a speaking convention.
My only consolation was that no one seems to care about him much. They didn't in the elections and they didn't last night at the convention. So much the better for America and the Constitution.
If Mitt Romney represents anything like the future of the Republican Party, we are in trouble. I anxiously await McCain's speech...
Saturday, August 30, 2008
Introducing the New VP
So, in 2008, Obama picked someone to reassure us all that he would collect seasoned political thinkers when he arrived in office. The choice was almost too measured, too safe. It didn't excite anyone. It didn't change anyone's mind (if the polls are to be believed). For McCain, the issue seemed just as urgent. At 72 and already evincing some disturbing lapses on the campaign trail (although he has kept a runner's pace that belies his age), everyone knows the VP choice would be important. The VP, after all, is one heartbeat from the presidency.
So he chose . . . Sarah who? It was a surprising move, to say the least. But, considering the framework of analysis above, it makes perfect sense. McCain needs to appeal to young voters. To women voters. He has been excoriated for being out of touch, and this gets him in good with the youth (as does, by the way, appearing with Daddy Yankee).
But given the kind of campaign that McCain and his supporters are running, the choice seems strange, and almost schizophrenic. McCain castigates his rival for not having the appropriate experience, and he chooses a 40 year old newbie as a potential successor. McCain runs ads aimed at disaffected Hillary Clinton supporters, then winks and nods at them as he trots out a woman to stand behind him. In short, this smacks of cynicism, clumsy politics, and--although it is probably much too early to tell at this point--desperation.
Sarah Palin is an unknown to me, and the VP pick (let's face it) should not be too important in terms of voting for a president. But it is the first glimpse of how a president would select advisers and cabinet members. We all know and remember the disasters of the Bush White House, which managed somehow to best the Clintons at cronyism and tried to turn the Justice Department into a kennel of conservative fighting dogs. It matters, in short, who these presidential candidates choose in the second position because we need to be assured that the president who comes to office will make wise decisions.
So, sorry McCain. This choice is a bit of the strange and a pinch too cynical to be of value. And I doubt you have really fooled anyone.
Friday, July 25, 2008
Cosmopolitan Education and Pedagogy: Liberal Education in the 21st Century
One cannot accurately engage liberalism without coming to a realization that implies an inherent pluralism in terms of human flourishing. In other words, a liberal perspective on life is conceptually an autonomous one—one that gives ample recognition and encouragement to personal development as one sees fit under the assumption that there will be equal recognition (because of inherent dignity) for everyone’s ability to also do the same so long as one’s own personal development does not encroach on the ability of another to also flourish. This liberal abstraction meets certain bulwarks as we begin to consider the institution of the public school, and dynamics of identity.
This Liberal idea of autonomous identity can be cause of political strife if we consider the debate over what should be taught in schools regarding identity claims and the seeming acceptance or recognition of some, and not others—Christian let’s say and not lesbian and gay. Again, this liberal idea of identity has resulted in substantial national and ethnic political debate over just what the truth is and at times resulting on a turn on the liberal state’s premise of acknowledging a person’s identity and protecting each person’s ability to flourish. Conflicting claims to identity-flourishing are not easily solvable by experts or ad hoc committees,-- and when considering claims of morality, which arguably lead to notions of identity, there aren’t any experts or supreme authorities to settle these moral arguments once and for all (take the debate on evolution and intelligent design for example and the gradation of opinions therein).
So, then, with these often conflicting metaphysical projections in the liberal state, educating children in many ways requires preparing them for an autonomous relationship with the dignity and autonomy of others. Because one, we as humans are not capable of developing on our own. Two, we are inextricably tied to others via relationships (parents, friends, lovers, family, children, neighbors, etc.). And perhaps third, because the things we come to value that concern the arts, the culture, money, food from other places, depend on the network of society. To be sure, we should not assume that the school has the primary role in educating children—we can rightly assume that parents have the central role. While it is true that the state may disagree with parents on how to teach children, the parents do not lose their roles. The state, in my own and the view of other philosophers, should intervene to protect the child’s growth into autonomy by promoting the notion of choices among options so that one, the child is aware of the choices of others by virtue of their equal dignity and autonomy, and two, the child’s parents still have the role of primary instruction when it comes to raising their children, and three, for the child to make the decisions that would lead her into autonomy.
Another problem then occurs if we accept this notion of choices among options within the school setting. How does this doctrine, then, suggest proper pedagogical methodology? In particular, if we hold true to the choices among options doctrine, we then should not omit some options. In the West, we have a peculiar way of asserting Euro-influenced methodologies essentially negating the other options other groups of people have come to raise and educate their children. For example, Harvard Economics Professor, Roland Fryer mentioned recently on CNN’s Black in America that African-American students perform lower than children in third-world countries. In many ways we could argue that all the options aren’t being afforded to children via routes to autonomy because those options have been restricted to a Euro-American sensibilities and politics of pedagogy while giving arguably proper avenue to place some responsibility on parents (or the lack thereof) which may lead to other critical forces causing such disparity. How, then, should the liberal state decide on a curriculum teleologically aimed at autonomy? Better yet, how can the liberal stat ensure it?
There is immediately the problem of what we can all agree the truth is (take religious education which preaches certain things about homosexuality and abortion). There is also the conflict of how much weight to place on different topics often among the same topic. Consider what I call the Lincoln paradox: In American history, just how much focus should be placed, pedagogically, to his decision to emancipate the slaves? Lincoln is generally depicted as a pariah of social justice given his time, but of what mention is equally often given of the political benefits of the emancipation for Union forces and of how he did not view blacks as equal to whites? The issue is not what the facts are, but which ones we should focus on as we teach children about events, ideas, and subjectivities—not just what happened, but what narratives those lessons are wed in. Kwame Anthony Appiah argues that since children are not readily able to absorb truth in all of its complexity, we must begin with simplified truths and perhaps what is even untrue. For example, we are taught untruth when we learn physics: We learn Newton and Maxwell before we learn Einstein and Schrödinger. Newton and Maxwell, he says did not know about relativity or about interdeterminancy of fundamental physical laws and so their physics which assumes absolute space and infinite divisibility is just not true. Perhaps this argument does not hold as much water when we move from concrete mathematical principles to the subjectivities of the mind, but maybe there is something to it all.
This “subjectivity problem” in education is highly critical because subjectivity arises generally from some interaction with the world (or lack thereof) and there are notions of intersubjectivity as noted by Sartre and also W.E.B. Du Bois’ thesis of double consciousness which unquestionably play a role in how people become aware of choices among options. And since subjectivity is a necessary child of autonomy certain claims of truth are made based on identity and of moral reasoning which are both plural by liberal nature. To these problems, Kwame Anthony Appiah suggests that a compromise should at least be considered. He states that when identity claims are at stake, parents are permitted to insist that their children not be taught what is contrary to their beliefs and in turn the state insists that the child be told what others believe in the name of a desire for the sort of mutual knowledge across identities that is a condition for living productively together.
Thursday, June 12, 2008
History, blood, and war
Although complicated, the facts leading to Boumediene v. Bush may be somewhat succinctly stated. The 2001 Authorization for Use of Military Force (AUMF) passed by Congress in the wake of the September 11 attacks gave President Bush authority to seek retribution on Afghanistan’s Taliban-led government. In the subsequent war, prisoners were kept in Afghanistan prisons or shipped to the American Naval Station at Guantanamo Bay. These prisoners of war were styled “enemy combatants,” a status crafted by the executive branch to bolster claims that the POWs were not to be granted any of the rights determined by the Geneva Conventions. The Supreme Court ruled in Hamdi v. Rumsfeld (2005) that this situation was intolerable, and that the executive branch could not make such a determination by itself. Congress responded with the Military Commissions Act (MCA) of 2006, which (along with providing legislative backing to the executive branch’s military commissions) stripped federal courts of habeas corpus jurisdiction.
So, when several detainees petitioned for writs of habeas corpus, Boumediene among them, the D.C. Court of Appeals dismissed the petitions because Congress had stripped the court of its jurisdiction. It was precisely this issue that came before the U.S. Supreme Court in Boumediene v. Bush. And the Supreme Court’s firm answer (if predicated on a very slim majority) is that habeas corpus is a judicial power that Congress cannot suspend unless within the bounds of the Constitution.
Although the opinions are awash in technical legal argument, both the opinion of the court and the dissenters rely on competing historical narratives. Justice Kennedy, both the swingman and the author of the majority opinion, constructed a sweeping historical narrative of the writ of habeas corpus that spans eight centuries. Relying on the amicus brief filed by legal historians, Kennedy described the principle of habeas corpus as originating on the field at Runnymede in 1215, of growing up in tandem with the king’s power in the fourteenth century, and emerging in the seventeenth as a judicial check on the absolutist pretensions of the Stuart monarchs. The various political and military conflicts between king and parliament in the seventeenth century are cast by Kennedy as crucial in the development of habeas corpus as a check against arbitrary power. The victory of parliamentary forces and the constitutional settlement of 1689 reaffirmed the common law rights of trial by jury and habeas corpus and created a lasting tradition for Anglo-Saxon constitutionalism in the face of arbitrary power. American patriots breathed this same rhetoric in the Revolutionary period a century later, and insured in their Constitution that neither Congress nor the executive could suspend habeas corpus except in very clear cases (rebellion or invasion).
Kennedy’s narrative is generally correct, even if it lacks a certain amount of historical sophistication. It is right where it matters most—for instance, in identifying the writ of habeas corpus’s change from a prerogative writ concerned with power (and solidifying the king’s power in the fourteenth century) to one concerned with liberty in the seventeenth century. And Kennedy’s narrative is aspirational, one that recognizes the substance of American revolutionaries’ very real commitment to liberty and their desire that the Constitution be interpreted in this way.
Compare this with the narrative sketched by Antonin Scalia. To quote from his dissenting opinion: “America is at war with radical Islamists.” This is a war he traces back to 1983 and the bombing of the Marine barracks in Lebanon that killed 241 American soldiers and which moves to American soil in 2001. The enemy (always referred to by Scalia in the singular) “has threatened further attacks against our homeland.” He adds that one need only to “board a plane anywhere in the country, to know that the threat is a serious one.” We have sent our armed forces “against the enemy, in Afghanistan and Iraq.” For Scalia, the decision reached by the Supreme Court today “will make the war harder on us. It will almost certainly cause more Americans to be killed.”
This is Scalia’s narrative—blood, war, and executive power. Accusing the Court of playing a “bait-and-switch” game with the president, he has linked the judicial check to a war apparently begun in 1983 in Lebanon and which has presumably a beginning, middle, and (eventually) an end. But the ambiguities and distortions that lurk behind Scalia’s ham-fisted history belie his argument. Hezbollah (the perpetrators of the 1983 attack on the U.S. Marines barracks) and Al Qaeda are two very different organizations that come from rival Muslim sects. They do not cooperate. Linking such attacks on U.S. troops abroad is at best a callous display of ignorance. At worst it is intellectually dishonest. At the very least, his refusal to consider the civilian casualty count in the Middle East—those who have born the brunt of our war on terror as well as the brunt of terrorist attacks. Such facts are apparently nuisances to Scalia. So much the worse for historical truth.
Nonetheless, Scalia’s positioning of historical narrative before legal argument in his dissent is an indication of just how important historical narrative is. Why else would he begin his dissent with such a narrative? His legal analysis is formal and chilly, and it fails to persuade in the face of basic constitutional principles, let alone the litany of human rights abuses that we are perpetrating in an attempt to “protect” us. Scalia must know this, otherwise he would not need to justify his legal reasoning with an historical narrative that places Boumediene v. Bush into the context of a perpetual war (a war going on 25 years long, if Scalia’s narrative is accepted). Only then can the government’s extreme action of suspending habeas corpus and trying foreign nationals by military commission make sense. But the colossal failure of his historical narrative intellectually and morally indicates that not all narratives are equal. And our ability to receive them critically and to reject them when they fail is a key component in the survival of constitutional democracy.
Thursday, May 29, 2008
Fairness, Foulness, the Formalist/Realist Split and the . . . NBA
Was it a foul? Fish clearly bumped Barry on the shooting arm while he was in the process of trying to dribble out of coverage to either make the pass or put up a three. But not only was there no whistle, but not even the Spurs afterwards said a foul should have been called. If Brent Barry--who initially threw up his hands in frustration--says there was no foul, why should we think there was one? Perhaps because the league office has now reviewed the play and said there should have been a foul called.
There are four major arguments at play in the ongoing debate on whether the Lakers escaped fate on Tuesday. Interestingly, these arguments parallel problems faced by judges when tricky issues come before them. Briefly, here are the arguments:
1) It WAS a foul. A defensive player who has left his feet is out of position, Fisher had done so, collided with Barry, and it would be a foul at any time during the game. The game should be refereed the same from minute one to minute forty-eight.
2) NO foul. In a last possession play at the end of a game (especially one so momentous) shooters shoot and defenders defend and the players, not the referees, will decide the game.
3) FOUL, but it would be FOUL TO CALL IT. The Lakers had just lost possession on the other end because of a miss-call by the referees. This occurred when a shot by Fisher glanced off the rim, but the shot clock was not reset. Thus, advantage Spurs. Now, at the other end, a non-call on the foul makes it even (rather than giving the advantage to the Lakers).
4) It's BARRY'S FAULT. Brent Barry didn't sell the foul. If he sold the foul, he would have got the call. But he didn't. Barry's problem.
We can find in these arguments major schools of adjudication, believe it or not. Position 1 is akin to FORMALISM. A foul is a foul, no matter where it occurs. The rulebook tells you what a foul is. It's akin to stepping out of bounds. If a player steps out of bounds, then he turns the ball over. Doesn't matter when it happens.
Position 2 is the REALIST response to formalists. Of course rules are rules, say the realists, but the truth of the matter is that they are applied subjectively and within other, informal rules. For instance, everyone knows that superstars get calls that role players don't. And everyone knows that in the final seconds of the game, you don't try to draw offensive or defensive fouls because the referees will let you play. Few Bulls fans (or Jazz fans, for that matter) will forget Michael Jordan's famous shot in game six of the 1998 Finals (Bulls led the series 3-2 at that point). Down 85-86, Jordan cleared Byron Russell out of his way before taking the shot that put the Bulls ahead. Should a foul have been called? No, say the realists. Do we want our memory of NBA great games to be people standing on the line shooting free throws to end a game, or letting people put up shots and live or die in the moment? Let's be real.
Positions 3 and 4 are both outliers to the formalist/realist debate suggesting ways in which real circumstances mitigate the absolute rules. Position 3 takes an EQUITABLE approach. Make up calls are, after all, a part of any sport, and moreso for basketball where fouls are acknowledged as the most subjective part of refereeing. Position 4 is something akin to blame the victim. The real point, though, is not that Barry should be criticized for not "selling" the foul, but rather that if Barry had gone tumbling head over toe and lost the ball out of bounds after Fish bumped him, the referees would have had no choice but to call the foul (or, at least, it would be harder for them to ignore it).
Being more a realist than a formalist, I think the refs got it right. And I don't think the Spurs are served well by the league patting them on the shoulder and saying "sorry, guys, Barry should have been on the line to send the game into overtime." The Spurs evidently don't either, but they may just be keeping a good face. No one wants to be seen as a whiner. And, regardless of what OUGHT to have happened, what IS happening is that the Spurs have to win three in a row, with or without the benefit of good calls, informal rules, and all that jazz.
Wednesday, May 28, 2008
The Ethics of Tolerance
No doubt that many have heard the recent comments Sen. Clinton made connecting the length of the Democratic Primaries, former pres. Clinton, and the assassination of Robert Kennedy to the month of June. The general argument Sen. Clinton attempted to make was that compared to previous democratic primaries, the contest we are all witnessing is not as long. This is not quite true. By June of 1992, former pres. Clinton did get the nomination, but (this is according to Tim Russert and others) in the six weeks prior to, a vast majority in the Democratic Party were ceding the nomination to him simply because he had a massive delegate lead insurmountable by the upcoming contests. In June of 1968, Robert Kennedy was not in the same position as former pres. Clinton to clinch the nomination. He was actually looking forward to going to Chicago and focusing on later primaries, and we all know what tragically happened next.
What is troubling about Sen. Clinton’s premises is at least threefold:
1. The way Sen. Clinton juxtaposed her reasoning for continuing on was, arguably, rather parsimonious.
2. The facts of the events Sen. Clinton cited were not fully articulated.
3. Referencing Robert Kennedy in June of 1968, and particularly only mentioning his assassination which Sen. Clinton did, as rationale, neglects America’s original political sin and arguably takes a matter of instantiated historical fact and sentiment and attempts to place it in an objective realm of reason.
The basis of premise three is perhaps most important because it references an age-old philosophical problem that poked at David Hume for quite some time. The question, then, becomes how do you make something that “is” what “ought” to be? In other words, how does/can the instantiated fact of Robert Kennedy’s assassination (the ‘is’), become part of the acceptable rationale to Sen. Clinton continuing her campaign (a rationale for what ‘ought’ to be a reason for her continued campaign)? Perhaps such an argument could be better held in favor of Sen. Clinton if she would have considered premise two more properly. For our discussion though, we shall move on the words that were spoken.
II. The Vagueness of Identity
I’ve spoken to about a handful of people about this matter; all varying in age, ethnicity, class, and training. And though it is difficult to place the thoughts and feelings of a few as complete and total rationales, I did notice connections between the opinions in conversations held and certain views of identity my friends have about themselves. Perhaps these views on identity could be used as a connective tool to interpret why varied opinions were held on this issue and just what could be done with those sentiments to not further any divides. Anyhow, concerning identity, there appears at least thus far in my studies two prisms which it can be shaped. One concerns the picture of romanticism—the idea of “finding,” or “authenticating” oneself. The other suggests a more existentialist picture (shout out to John Paul Sartre)—the doctrine of “existence precedes essence”: meaning that one exists first and has to decide what exactly to exist as. In other words, we have certain materials available to us as far as identity goes. We then have to sift through the material and construct ourselves.
A middle view could be argued, as Kwame Anthony Appiah does that self-authorship is a good thing, but that authored identity must make some sense. And for that to happen, that identity must be constructed in response to facts outside oneself. These three positions could be further elucidated if we consider the period after the Civil War and more particularly what are known as the “Civil War Amendments.” We could make the argument that the 13th, 14th, and 15th amendments gave former slaves new “materials” (even though they faced a rather austere American society—which is an issue of sociability) to construct identities with—to give them an essence consisting of citizenship, due process, etc. In the passing of these amendments, those in congress had the opportunity and venues to not only exercise a sense of moral justice, but to “authenticate“ the ideals of America. The middle view would suggest that both extremes essentially came together to make sense for all involved and are constructed in response to certain facts (the Constitution, Declaration of Independence, The Bill of Rights or the very amendments themselves). So how does this relate to how we respond to Sen. Clinton?
I argue, especially given the historical connections of the assassination of popular political leaders such as Robert Kennedy, Dr. Martin Luther King Jr. and Malcolm X, The nature of Sen. Obama being in a position to win the Democratic Party nomination and his being a popular political leader, and those who gravitate either by inclination or generous thought to either of the mentioned venues of identity, could arrive at varied interpretations of Sen. Clinton’s words. Interpretations which arguably include the understanding of the other views based on the roads of identity we’ve discussed which implies a notion of toleration for those that oppose one that someone may hold.
III. The Difficulty of Tolerance
With all we’ve discussed, it may seem more acceptable (I would hope so at least) that we may understand why it is that differences of opinion occur among people that come across the same thing or hear the same words. Outside logical connections and philosophical inquiry, resulting explanations and perhaps larger elements of truth are assaulted by unclear biases and peculiar norms. Bias is unfortunately real and so are the social norms that can emerge from them. It was on this notion that Victor Hugo rather accurately wrote “The human soul has still greater need of the ideal than of the real. It is by the real that we exist; it is by the ideal that we live” in his famous Hunchback of Notre Dame. So why then do we or should we value tolerance—especially since it can further another’s biases and make what is rather false very real? Harvard’s T.M. Scanlon argues that tolerance allows for a relation with one’s fellow citizens. Whether this relation is positive or abortive is still unclear, but in evaluating comments like the ones made my Sen. Clinton, one should perhaps realize that they are not made in objective vacuums and are attributable to not only goal-oriented biases and the training of authenticated or authored identity (or a mixture of the two), but are curiously enough, evaluated by the same means.
Dum vivimus, vivamus.